1. (page 178, # 4)
Now, we show that this ordering is a well-ordering.
Let
be nonempty. Let
.
Then
is a nonempty set of natural numbers and therefore has a least
element
. By definition of
, the set
is a
nonempty subset of
so that it, too, has a least
element which we call
. This
is the
-least element of
for
if
is any element of
, then
as
is
the least element of
and if
we have
as
is the least element of
.
The ordering looks lke case (d).
2 (page 178 # 7)
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
Naïvely,
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
Thus, if
and
we have
so that
.
Now, suppose that
. By definition, there is some
with
. By part (b) we have
.
Thus,
is a transitive superset of
.
3 (page 187, # 13)
4 (page 187, # 14)
Let be elements of
. Let
. By definition of
,
we have
so that
as well. That is,
.
As
we actually have
as desired.
5 (page 195, # 18)
For ordinals and
we know
or
.
Thus,
is
an ordinal and is the least upper bound of
with respect to
.
If has no greatest element, then its least upper bound cannot be an element.
That is,
. Moreover,
cannot be the successor
of some ordinal
for if
were a bound to
we would contradict
minimality of
and if it is not a bound to
, then there would be
some
with
implying
that
.
If has a greatest element, then that greatest element is the least upper bound,
.
19 (page 195 # 19)
We prove a slightly more general statement:
Proposition:
If are
are linearly ordered structures and
and
have the same finite
cardinality, then they are order isomorphic.
To prove the proposition, we need a lemma.
Lemma: Let be a finite nonempty linearly ordered set. Then
has a least element.
We are now in a position to prove the proposition.
If
, then for
or
write
where
is
the
-least element of
(given by the lemma) and
.
By the inductive hypothesis, there is an order isomorphism
.
Set
. As
,
is
a function. For
in
we see that necessarily
so that
. If
as well we have
.
Otherwise,
so that
. In either case, we see that
preserves the ordering and is thus injective. As any injective function
from a set of size
to a set of size
is bijective,
is an
order isomorphism.
7 (page 200, # 24)
8 (page 207, # 33)
For
, this inclusion is obvious as
.
For
, assuming that
, we note that
if
, then as
by definition, we
have
and
as
is transitive. Thus,
(by the inductive hypothesis). By
the hypothesis on the relation between
and
, we have
. As
was arbitrary in
, we have
.
Finally, for
a limit ordinal, we have
![]() |
![]() |
![]() ![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
Thus, our claim is proven. As every set is grounded, if then
for some
we have
so that
. Therefore,
.